Like Fukuyama’s “End of History” thesis, disproving Walzer’s universal-made-particular claim regarding morality seems difficult. Indeed, the quick example of the “Golden Rule,” an empathy-based dogma, finds itself in religions across the world. With my limited experience in this world, shaped by a firmly liberal, Western upbringing, I have a hard time speaking beyond my own perspective, but I would like to agree with Walzer’s claims regarding humanity. He claims that “humanity has members but no memory, and so it has no history and no culture,” and goes on to add, “the members of all the different societies, because they are human, can acknowledge each other’s different ways, respond to each other’s cries for help, learn from each other, and march (sometimes) in each other’s parades.” Again, I would love to believe that this is true or would one day be true, but it is too idealistic to have faith in. With a feeling of growing complexity in this world, it is hard to trust that empathy and a steadfast commitment to justice will prevail. With the dual tension of local conflict keeping many people preoccupied and global problems growing increasingly complex, responding to cries abroad seems unlikely (with the refugee crisis as a clear example). Indeed, it’s hard to argue that our thin morality offers us sufficient grounds to dive into problems that are often deeply shrouded in thick morality; can adequate faith in our thin morality convince us that we are solving others’ problems rather than worsening them? Certainly, it is difficult to be convinced by such arguments (along with Fukuyama’s and Ash’s) that focus on universal ideological convergence in an age where splintering feels never-ending as new battles continue to emerge. As such, perhaps my skepticism is solely related to my worries towards the world we live in; I would love to see an unimaginable surprise to dispel such doubts.
Author Archives: Brianna Bourne
We Can’t All Be Cardinal Arns
In A Miracle, A Universe, Lawrence Weschler describes the collaborative efforts between Jaime Wright and Cardinal Arns in documenting Brazil’s torture during a period of militarized dictatorship. The second of these two, Cardinal Arns, embodied morality as he evokes a sense of “uncoveredness,” arguing that “the true shall make you free,” (29-30). Moreover, as a religious leader, Cardinal Arns represented a steadfast commitment to enlightenment and coming to terms with all flaws within and around an individual. Cardinal Arns advocated for values everyone can achieve and would theoretically ameliorate society. However, in describing the judges of the torture cases, Weschler presents the difficulty in implementing Cardinal Arns’ practices in a specific aspect of Brazilian society. Weschler offers secondhand descriptions of judges “scowling and saying, ‘Don’t write it down–it’s a lie,'” (46), as well as the judges not wanting “things to descend to the level of a farce. There was a sense of minimum obligation,” (48). These portrayals offer insight into the broad spectrum of commitment to morality within Brazilian society of such an era. More critical too is the fact that such apathy towards the “truth” occurred within the courtroom. While Cardinal Arns offers a simple foundation towards the development of societal morality, such a feat incurs massive hurdles against institutions that fail to meet his level of acceptance. Certainly the truth may bring freedom, however such logic fails when applied to more than one person, as we each foster our own truths, with morality being a subjective matter. Therefore, with a moral pursuit being the worse of two imperfect solutions, taking a practical approach and building on a shared version of the truth might be the best remaining option.
Matching Expectations of Democracy in a Third Grade Classroom
Analyzing the portrayal of democracy in “Please Vote For Me” can be done with respect to either democracy in theory or in practice. As far as the former, on the surface, the third graders’ classroom’s version of democracy follows Dahl’s criteria: the election of officials, the right to vote, the right to run for office, the right to express themselves for all. However, the students are unable to fully achieve democracy due to a lack of appreciation for all the details of the democratic process, or democracy in practice. Specifically, as Schimitter and Karl argue, fairly conducted elections are crucial to democracy, and while there was indeed competition between the three students, bribery plays a role in giving the votes to Luo Lei. Neither were elected officials being held accountable for their actions: the students do not utilize their right to confront Luo Lei’s authoritarian manner. Also, Schmitter and Karl emphasize deliberation between the people as important to the democratic process, and the film doesn’t emphasize the students taking part in this (aside from interactions directly with the nominees who tried to sway them). The lack of these conversations could potentially be due to an apathy on the part of the students, a lack of caring that effectively destroys democracy as it removes the role of the citizens. Perhaps too however, the expectation of these students to practice democracy in their classroom is too great. In their setting, the students face two extremes with respect to social order: discipline outside the classroom and disorder within it. As far as the liberal democracy argument, the students must achieve order in the classroom (not the chaos of bullying one minute and everyone crying the next) before they can establish democracy. And ultimately, without knowing the terms associated with government (ie. vote, dictator, manager), they lack the insight about politics in general.
Movement in Modernization
In “The Grocer and the Chief,” Lerner certainly weaves into his report his own views regarding modernization, notably a favoritism towards the spreading of Westernized practices. For Lerner, progress seems to represent a sort of movement, but one in which American or Western values dominate. Indeed, he highlights two forms of mobility–physical and societal–that seem to be at the core of progress for Lerner. Upon the advent of bus transportation, Lerner describes, “the villagers were getting out of their holes at last,” (51). Though a paraphrase of the Grocer’s previous comment, this statement implies Lerner’s view of the villagers’ acquisition of freedom: a release from a former position of not simply immobility, but also ignorance (similar to Plato’s cave). This distinctly contrasts the Chief telling Tosun that he “‘wouldn’t move a foot from [Balgat],'” (49) and the shepherd (who eventually moved villages) would rather kill himself then leave Balgat. As such, Lerner approaches his analysis of modernization with a familiar approach that it greatly benefits the many, while potentially harming the few. The second form of mobility is societal, which the Grocer evokes initially upon responding to what he would do as Turkey’s president. The ease with which he offers his answer–to “make roads for the villagers to come to towns to see the world,” (49)–reveals his thoughtfulness. He had taken to formulate an answer to a question that might be more commonly asked in democratic republics, where representatives listen to citizens voices. Similarly, the movement of agricultural to factory jobs results in a desire to gain capital, that villagers could later spend on refrigerators, tractors, trucks, and radios–the last of which giving them power that formerly only the Chief held.
Lerner’s evaluation of Turkey’s societal changes accentuates his biases as he promotes Westernized values, like various forms of mobility. While obvious to readers accessing such judgments, the next question to ask regards the extent to which Lerner himself is aware of his partiality. Having grown up in a country that praises its own “achievements,” I simply wonder to what extent it is possible to prevent my own biases from leaking through too.
Breaking a Key Rule: Gessen’s Overly-Broad Research Scope
In “The Dying Russians” Masha Gessen takes into consideration a puzzle that started out as an obvious source of confusion for her. She explains her personal relationships to those who died somewhat under the radar (of her knowledge): “her friend,” a “newspaper reporter [she’d] seen a week earlier,” (2). She goes on to revealing how she “cried on a friend’s shoulder” (3), and the difficulty of processing these deaths. While this emotionality doesn’t necessarily have to affect her research, it may well have lead her to remain so wedded to the question of deaths over the course of her study. What her question (why Russians are dying in numbers) becomes, however, is beyond any scope of a successful research endeavor. From the post-war period to present day, Gessen’s time frame yields only in size to the vastness of her country in study. Perhaps in an attempt to do justice to this broad scope, Gessen endeavors to analyze an extensive data set, from Parsons’s more anthropological approach with her “months-long conversation” (2), to Eberstadt’s historical-trend based research. Between these two examinations, contradictory conclusions arise, like whether a younger or more middle-aged population represents the dying population. While I do respect and appreciate her comprehensive collection of evidence, I simply find it as a result of her inability to narrow down the scope of her research question. Indeed, such a broad question certainly can lead an investigator down several avenues of more specific research, and she might have been better off following one rather than sticking to her more general puzzle, for which she demonstrates a difficulty to explain with specific answers, as one would expect.
Orwell’s Got the Power–of the Pen, But Could That Be It?
In “Shooting an Elephant,” Orwell presents himself as being the individual with the least agency. In his position as a British officer, he describes his “hatred of the empired [he] served and [his] rage against the evil-spirited little beasts,” (1). Orwell’s insecurity abroad leaves him vulnerable to manipulation, and he ultimately serves a will that is not his own. As such, following Havel’s definition of power, Orwell’s mind and body work as one, so as to serve will that directly contrasts the dominated’s beliefs. The Burmese people also derive their power in the manner Scott describes in Weapons of the Weak, via an anonymous, “two-thousand” (3) person crowd’s constant retaliation to the White Man’s presence. Via the collection of insults towards Orwell, they develop a firm grasp on his psyche, instilling self-doubt in his vulnerability, and they ultimately display their power in getting him to shoot the elephant.
Orwell’s first-hand account, however, must be taken as such–a personal rendition of his insecurity abroad. While he offers a variety of powerful candidates–the British Imperialists, the Burmese population–he yield the piece’s climax over to the elephant’s death. By ending with a description of amazement towards event–”thick blood welled out of him like red velvet, but still he did not die,” (4)–Orwell may be offering a new viewpoint as to who yields the most power: the “great beast” (2,4) himself. Moreover, this final turn could reveal further insight into the shame with which he follows the will of the Burmese, and thus too his desire to shift the narrative so as to mask this inner turmoil.
Williams College: Player or Played Member of the Education System?
In Gatto’s “Against School,” he notes, “compulsory schooling was to make a sort of surgical incision into the prospective unity of these underclass,” (36). In my second-hand experience, the public school system certainly does this, by operating on local funding, and allowing subtle inequalities to arise depending on a region’s income level, thus determining a school’s quality. I would add to Gatto’s argument that while disunifying the bottom of the ladder, the nation’s school system indeed brings the upper echelon together in higher education. While independent efforts are fighting to change this aspect of the college admission process, accessibility depends on a student’s means, thereby resulting in the amalgamation of individuals of a certain financial status. Again, many institutions (including Williams) attempt to fight this current within the system, but can only do so to a point. Our college maintains its elitism by offering preferential admission to students of legacy status and athletes, the latter often reflecting increased availability to necessary resources. While this previous claim may be controversial, the fact that Williams prides itself on selecting top students is not, and oftentimes tutors, some form of test-prep, or simply secondary school with great resources hide behind those outstanding GPAs and test scores. With its sizable barriers to entry, I believe that Williams certainly plays a role in maintaining power in the elite, producing–albeit liberally educated–citizens to sustain and pass on the authority to the next generation (via alumni connections perhaps). Moreover, in maintaining a large endowment, the College acknowledges the role such wealth can have in boosting its prestige, thereby reflecting an awareness of rankings at the institutional—rather than the individual as in Gatto’s discussion—level. While simultaneously perpetuating the problem, the College remains stuck within the system as well, and thus can solely redefine the education system within such confines.