Contradictions in the Source of Modernity

In Khomeini’s arguments, the source of modernity, indeed the source of everything is undoubtedly Islam. There is no need for an individual to look further, because the Qur’an and its interpreters will provide the answers. However, this does leave out how modernity might be achieved by those tasked with adapting the Qur’an to the modern era. A point Tabaar repeatedly raises is the constant fluidity of Khomeini’s Velayat-e Faqih as his political needs adapted and changed. An example of this follows the Green Movement, which left many of Khomeini’s advisors in a negative public light. They had all committed some wrong in the view of Khomeini’s doctrine, and thus were demonized by the conservative populace. As is reviewed in Chapter 10, Khomeini was forced to reform his ideas, replacing strict rigidity with a fluid doctrine that allowed for a rapidly changing world. This then means, at least for a few individuals, there must be some external source of modernity. There must be something outside of the sacred text that guides its interpretation. This begs the question, what is that source?

Following the same example, it could be argued that this new source is the collective will of the people. If they are angry, change the doctrine to please them. But, then it would have been easier to simply punish those they were angry at, rather than alter a supposedly fixed text. I think the source is something much more complicated than that. A cynic might argue that Khomeini and his supporters had no belief in a “fixed truth” and that they were simply acting in whichever way is most fitting of their agenda, but I don’t think that’s the case. I think that, for the leaders of the Islamic Republic, there exists a sort of in between. Their source of modernity draws from a mixture of the sacred, of the will of the people, of their own personal agendas. For them, modernity is as fluid as Velayat-e Faqih.

Modernity’s Basis

I don’t think Tabaar’s text equips us to make generalized claims about modernity’s basis as a phenomenon broadly, especially because it’s so difficult to speak in terms of necessary/ sufficient preconditions. In the case of Iran, though, I think one of the answers to the question of “on what basis” that Tabaar implies is that there is always a negotiation between these two sources of modern truth (which echoes the needs of each of the competing promises of modernity), to borrow the phrasing of the question. His book clearly presents the idea that the divine/ governmental aspect, the imposed modernity, was essential for actually enacting reforms, making decisions, and for shaping the will of the people (for which Islam and religious arguments were used), but was imbued with power through its claim to legitimacy, which was affirmed through the assent of the people.

This dynamic surfaces in his discussion of Khomeini’s influence being derived from the support of the people as well as the way Khomeini later draws upon this to remind the people of their role in giving him power. In responding to his critics and attempting to delegitimize their critiques– particularly clerics– following the issuing of the fatwa against Rushdie, for example, he emphasized that they used to support the separation of politics and religion (a model opposite that which Khomeini advocated and the people had supported), and that he had made the “‘slogan of overthrowing the Shah’ a reality”– he had realized the vision of the future supported by the people (195). By arguing that “the imperialists were using these pseudo-religious-nationalist figures to sow doubt in the society,” he is reaffirming his position as the legitimate voice, reminding the people that they, though possibly now doubting their initial position, had once fully supported it and brought it into being– it was theirs, not just Khomeini’s (ibid). By taking the modern position of the representative of the people’s will, he is also invoking ‘modern’ notions of legitimate power being rooted in the consent of the governed.

Pragmatism and Khomeini

The first important point that Tabaar wants emphasized is that in his conception, politics drive Islamic ideologies. Interestingly, he sidesteps Seligman’s concerns in Modernity’s Wager by arguing that authentic Islamic beliefs can be shaped by political concerns. Likewise, belief’s can be shaped to meet political ends without losing their significance and authority. Thus, Tabaar’s implicit argument is that the sacred can be contingent without losing its sacrality. The same principle can be extended to the questions of authority the book raises.

This flexibility is highlighted in Khomeini’s “increasing pragmatism”(189) which Tabaar points to on numerous occasions. The most profound turn for Tabaar was Khomeini’s shift from arguing that an Islamic government is necessary to uphold shari’a to saying Islamic law could be broken in order to protect the state. A fundamentally pragmatic change, which is reminiscent of Machiavelli. Ultimately, though religion is a part of Iranian modernity, it does not define a static and immutable course. Human subjectivity and pragmatism is, for Tabaar, the root of Iranian political development. Though there have been attempts to hide this reality, as when Khomeini issued his famous fatwa against Salman Rushdie, the longer political events follow their practical and somewhat banal patters, the less important Islam will become for Iranian politics.

Religious Statecraft and Modernity

 

In his work, Religious Statecraft: The Politics of Islam in Iran, Mohammad Ayatollahi Tabaar traces half a century of shifting Islamist doctrines to demonstrate that religious narratives in Iran can change in accordance with elite attempts to consolidate and augment power. In this account, Tabaar explains that competing political actors strategically develop Shi’a-inspired ideologies to gain credibility and raise mass support. Taken as a whole, Tabaar’s work depicts Iranian politics as a system in which power drives Islamist ideology.

Using this work as a framework for analyzing the posited question, it is clear how elites derive and construct authority to achieve modernity. In Tabaar’s account, Islam is used as means of gaining authority for political ends, including the attempt to achieve modernity. To the extent that the public views these uses of Islam as authentic, they can be said to be legitimized in the eyes of the public. The elites here, or faqih, guide and shape the opinions of the masses in order to achieve their ends. Note, this is not to say that these elites do not believe in Islam or that their statuses as Muslims are purely ploys for power. Instead, the argument is that the ways in which Islamist ideology are articulated are driven by power and political necessity.

In this depiction, the will of the public is used to mobilize and effectuate change, such as the attempt to achieve modernity. The consent of the people is necessary as modernity cannot be achieved without it, but this consent is ultimately guided and constructed by elites through Islamist ideologies.

Death of (to?) Dichotomy

In Chapter 4 of “Religious Statecraft,” “Insitutionalizing Velayat-e Faqih,” there appears a political disagreement which I believe characterizes much of Iranian politics in the surge and wake of Khomeini’s popularity. Mohammad Shariatmadari, an influential Iranian cleric, at first disagrees with Khomeini’s view of the Islamic Government, believing that clerics do not belong in politics. The dichotomous spirit of Shariatmadari – the same thought process which had so long separated the largely “secular” government from the frankly clerical matters of the clerical class – died with the rise of Khomeini. From 1979 on, the sacred and the mundane became inseparable. From 1979 on, to criticize the government was to criticize God, because the government represents God in the velayat-e faqih. When it came down to the March 1979 referendum – Islamic Government or not – Shariatmadari backed down because he could not manage to negotiate his way out of believing, or at least pretending to believe, that the government governed by Islam is the ideal government. In this, the rigidity of Islam rears its head. Even though political Islam is malleable enough to allow for Marxism, governmental Platonism, dictatorship, democracy, or Khomeinism, it is not malleable enough for Shariatmadari, and indeed all devout Muslims (demonstrated by the fact that the new constitution was approved by 98.2% of voters), to believe that these “political Islam”s, or these plural “politics of Islam,” whether Marxist or Khomeinist, do not come from Islam if it is truly the ideal government. In this sense, the schizophrenia of the Islamic public, which ultimately is forced to choose Islam by its own devoutness, still largely believes that the Islamic government of Iran (lowercase g) today does not represent the truly ideal political Islam, which is seen by the continuance of public protests and contemporaneous drop in revolutionary fervor. It would appear that the Iranians are attempting to mold for themselves a subjective objectivity. Iran deeply desires the true Islamic Government (capital g) from on High, but wants just as deeply to define this Islamic Government for themselves, starting with the confessional unmasking of the state as imperfect.

Religious Statecraft: The Zenith of Modernity?

In determining “on what basis, modernity?” through the context of Tabaar’s text, I am not convinced that the answer lies “with the cleansing influence of the sacred” (as represented by the faqih) or “the consent of the ruled.” There has to be some force mediating between the two; in the Iranian case this is the complex bureaucratic state apparatus that, as discussed in class, would be exceedingly difficult to undermine even in the event of a leadership coup or crisis.
Did Khomeini use power as a tool for implementing religion or religion as a tool for attaining and maintaining power? Tabaar clearly illustrates that it is the latter, most forcefully through his explanation of how Khameini rose to leader despite his lack of religious qualifications. On page 200, Tabaar tells us that “Velayat-e Faqih followed politics as opposed to the other way around.” If modernity is a curve, to me this is a natural step in said curve’s progression. It is not the blind following of religion (which “Westoxified modernity” so scorned) nor is it trust in a realm of pure reason not anchored in any religious or moral virtue. Instead it represents the use of human rationalization to pragmatically combine religion with a modern political system to satisfy various factions and consolidate power. “The cleansing influence of the sacred” was manipulated to manufacture the “consent of the ruled,” thus creating a functioning system ostensibly rooted in religious values yet also considered a republic. This, of course, is very Machiavellian.
The power of the Iranian regime perhaps lies in the fact that there is not just one “reasoning individual” who has seen the light outside the cave and disperses the knowledge it provided. Rather, there are multiple leaders (e.g. Rafsanjani and Khameini and the members of various Councils) who derive their legitimacy from different sources and thus, when united in a given message, can be very difficult to refute. For example, the Assembly of Experts, Rasfajani, and certain Ayatollahs all used Islam in justifying the choice of a Supreme Leader that could be seen as breaking with recent Islamic tradition in the country. Through a concentrated campaign to publicly perpetuate Khameini’s legitimacy, they were able to effectively “re-craft” the state in Khomeini’s absence.

Revisited: On What Basis, Modernity?

In one of our first blogs, I asked you, “On what basis, modernity?”  Religious Statecraft gives us an opportunity to revisit the question, but with a sharper empirical focus on the relationship between sources of legitimacy, authority, and modern outcomes.  Take the questions below about Machiavelli and apply them to Tabaar’s text:  How is Iran, as a matter of practice and of policy, becoming modern?

On what basis, modernity—through the cleansing influence of the sacred, via the guidance of a faqih, or jurisprudent?  Or is modernity to be achieved by the consent of the ruled, the “flock,” as it were, the ummah?  Or is there a balance or negotiation between these two sources of modern “truth?”  What is the balance between the sacred, the fixed, and the contingent, and could it be that the public will embodies both of these, as we discussed in class?   You don’t need to answer all of these questions, but please use specific answers and examples drawn from Religious Statecraft.

From September 18, 2018:

The fragility of control plays a prominent if under appreciated role in Machiavelli’s The Prince.  In contrast to Lerner’s triumphalism (“I had it on top authority that during the summer of 1950 they had entered History”) or the harrowing implacability of “the Party” in Darkness at Noon, Machiavelli describes a world of constant variability and uncertainty.  No prince, no matter how savvy or cruel, can rest easy on his throne, circumstances and the variability of being his constant and insuperable foes.

Machiavelli leads us to the conclusion that there are no universal solutions, no easy recipes or checklists to follow in pursuing “the modern,” however defined.  Origins, the circumstances of coming combine with unforeseen events to make modernization a project forever uncertain and under siege.

We might ask, then, On what basis modernity?  The matter of legitimacy and authority has been at stake these past two weeks, whether of the Shah, of the multitude who comprise “the many,” or of the reasoning individual, who having adjusted his or her sights to the light outside of the cave, comes back to dispense capital-T Truth.  What or who is the source of modernity?  Might it be the individual, reaching for truth in the realm of the profane?  Or does modernity require the ballast of “fixed truths,” of a sacred authority that lies outside of the will and reason of the individual?  Might History be that source, or religion itself?  How might authority be reconciled to the individual will?

Abdolkarim Soroush

 

Abdolkarim Soroush was a follower of the line of thought largely generated by Karl Popper’s distinction between what he called “science” and “pseudoscience,” which revolutionized many rationalist European, American, and Islamic lines of thought, as well as the evolution of the philosophy of science, most notably during the time when the evolution of science itself was causing unforeseen challenges in the world in the technological world, with the rapid development of the atomic bomb occurring contemporaneously with Popper’s popularization. Soroush, like Popper, renounced Iranian Marxism as a result of this extremely calculated stance on ideology and science. Most interestingly, Soroush remained a devout Muslim for the remainder of his life, and wrote many of his books on Islam and religious belief within a philosophical mindset. The existence of “Soroushes” in the world, especially in extremely culturally devout countries like Iran, at least partially shows the ignorance with which the world “accepted to” modernity’s wager. As stated by Secor, Soroush, “as a man of faith, he had been educated to believe that man was immersed in an ocean of certainties, floating from one to the next. But as a student of philosophy, he came to see that instead a person drifted from conjecture to conjecture, doubt to doubt” (Secor 62). Soroush later emphasized the distinction between religion itself, which is perfect and eternal, and religious belief, which is, while well-founded, fallible and incomplete. All this is to say that while the West dove headfirst into a dichotomy between putting one’s belief in the sacred and putting one’s faith in one’s own authority (that infamous wager), Iran wrestled with the epistemological claims of infallibility; of religious belief as a thing to put faith in through the authority of the self, at least partially.

“I am a sick man…I am a wicked man”

What is modern about our readings this week?  What is particularly “western” or “eastern” about the narratives?  Is The Blind Owl a “Persian” story, Notes from Underground, Russian?  How might we read these books as literature, outside of their contexts?  Is it possible to do so, as art or as literature?

Do either of the narrators gain perspective, perhaps a moment of change?

It seems obvious that Dostoyevsky and Hedayat would agree that thinking too much, having the ability to see all sides of an issue or problem, leads to paralysis, what Tocqueville describes as the falling into the self.  How might solipsism be prevented or ameliorated?

Take a look at pg. 62 of The Blind Owl.  Hedayat speaks of a “real face” that emerges at the end of life.  What does he mean by this?

What do the two stories tell us about the relationship between the mind and the body?  Are the grotesqueries in The Blind Owl limited to the psychological, or does it extend to the physical (for example, the scenes from the butcher shop…)

Related to the above:  What are we to make of the closing comment by Richard Pevear in the Foreward to Notes from Underground, specifically his assertion that what “bedevils our century” is “that habit of substituting the psychological for the moral, of interpreting a spiritual condition as a kind of behavior?”

Sadegh Hedayat’s grave, Père Lachaise Cemetery, Paris, France

Study Notes for Modernity’s Wager, by Adam Seligman

 1.  Once you cut through the jargon, Seligman’s argument is premised on a simple claim:  Modernity’s wager rests on the notion that the individual, as an unfettered authority, will make the world better than one in which authority resides in the sacred.  Put plainly, moderns are hostile to authority other than their own.  Seligman’s assessment of how this bet has played out is grim.  Be prepared to explain why he is so skeptical of improvement, as well as what he sees as the consequences of this failed wager.
2.  Again, internal versus external sources of authority are the lynchpin of Seligman’s account of modernity.  Be ready to compare Seligman’s call for a return to the scared with Tocqueville’s prescription of “fixed beliefs.”  How might these be reconciled to individual freedom and autonomy, to modernity’s promise of emancipation and universal equality?
3.  Do you accept Seligman’s premise that modernity has called into being its own antitheses, in the form of fundamentalism, violence, etc.?  Are our lives fully transactional and measured by a calculus of exchange and choice?  Or do we still ethical lives, bound by an “irrational” (unreasoned) morality, unquestioned and taken on faith?
4.  The weakness of the individual in modernity, which we’ve discussed in the last two sessions, is highlighted rather clearly on pp. 49-50.  Please take a close look at this section.
5.  Consider the parable of Mr. Stern and the question of shame (pp. 72-77).  How does this imagined story relate to your own life, if at all?  Is this section coherent, or intelligible?